In a surprising turn, the classical legal language of constitutional principles and the development of doctrine is back with a vengeance. In United States v. Rahimi, the Chief Justice, writing for the Court, rejected a Second Amendment challenge to a federal statute that prohibits individuals subject to a domestic violence restraining order from possessing a firearm. “When an individual has been found by a court to pose a credible threat to the physical safety of another,” the Court held, “that individual may be temporarily disarmed consistent with the Second Amendment.”
Although there were a legion of concurrences, the concurring Justices also joined the majority opinion in full; only Justice Thomas dissented. Justice Thomas was the author of the Bruen decision two years ago, which announced an approach to the Second Amendment looking to the history and tradition of gun regulation and relevant analogues, taken at a low level of generality. That fact that Thomas dissented, and dissented alone, suggests strongly that something important has changed.
What has changed is that the Court, speaking through the majority opinion, has decided to approach the Second Amendment through an essentially classical lens. In a crucial methodological passage, the Chief Justice wrote that the proper inquiry is not a search for narrow historical analogues to founding-era regulation, but rather an attempt to discern “the principles that underpin our regulatory tradition…. Discerning and developing the law in this way is a commonplace task for any lawyer or judge.” (Internal quotations omitted; emphasis added). As though to emphasize the point, the Chief then repeated that “the law must comport with the principles underlying the Second Amendment, but it need not be a dead ringer or a historical twin” of traditional practices of gun regulation (internal quotation omitted; emphasis added). The relevant law is not to be understood as “trapped in amber.”
To be sure, the majority opinion claimed that its approach was consistent with the methodology of Bruen. But this was rather obviously a façon de parler, a standard and rather thin claim of methodological compatibility with a recent and important precedent. A concurrence by Justice Sotomayor, joined by Justice Kagan, underscored with approval that the Court, by invoking the language of constitutional “principles,” had substantially reinterpreted Bruen’s methodology. Thomas’ dissent, in pointed and revealing contrast both to the majority opinion and the Sotomayor concurrence, warned of “the dangers of approaches based on generalized principles” and cautioned the Court to “remain wary of any theory” that exchanges “the Second Amendment’s boundary line … for vague (and dubious) principles” (emphasis added). Although Thomas wisely did not directly and openly charge the majority with having abandoned the basic approach of Bruen - to do so would merely underscore his methodological defeat — it is not hard to read him as having said so implicitly, and with good reason. Any claim that the majority’s opinion is genuinely faithful to Bruen must argue, awkwardly, that Justice Thomas misunderstood or misapplied the methods of his own opinion, issued two years ago.
So too, Justice Gorsuch’s concurrence unmistakably took issue with the majority’s methodology, warning that if judges are allowed to “extrapolate their own broad new principles from [the] sources … no one can have any idea how they might rule” (emphasis added). He added, quoting the majority with some asperity, that “[a]s judges charged with respecting the people’s directions in the Constitution— directions that are ‘trapped in amber’ —our only lawful role is to apply them in the cases that come before us.” The opinions of the Justices whom one might call Originalists of the Strict Observance are palpably suffused with worry about the new methodological turn to constitutional principles, although to be sure that worry is prudently expressed.
To understand the intrinsically classical method of the majority opinion, quite different than Thomas’ approach, it helps to look back at the critiques of Bruen, and of Thomas’ narrow version of the history and tradition test, that have been offered by classical lawyers. With specific reference to Bruen, classical lawyers point to “the problem of originalist reliance on history only at specifically favored moments in time, rather than incorporating a broader understanding of the tradition in which they are embedded.” A broader understanding of this sort, for the classical lawyer, takes account of the enduring rational principles underlying the tradition and applies them to new circumstances, while preserving their shape and essence, as argued here, here and here.
In very much the same register, the Chief Justice offers an approach centered on what he calls, significantly, a “develop[ment] of the law,” rooted in the “principles” of the tradition rather than merely in specific historical data points, and aimed at “apply[ing] faithfully the balance struck by the founding generation to modern circumstances.” If this is still some version of originalism, it is an originalism so purposivist, so capacious, so open to reasoning from high-level principles, as to be operationally indistinguishable from non-originalism.
The aim of the development of the law, for the majority, is to preserve the essence of constitutional principles while applying them under changed conditions — the very enterprise that John Henry Newman urged in the parallel context of the development of theological doctrine, and that classical lawyers urge as itself the traditional approach to law over time. The classical approach holds that principles are enduring, but that as circumstances change, doctrine must itself “change in order to remain the same” - as Newman famously put it. As such, the classical approach offers a third way between two poles: one the one hand, Thomas’ strict data-point version of history and tradition, with analogues allowed only at low levels of generality; and on the other hand free-form “living constitutionalism,” in which the principles immanent in the tradition can themselves be re-evaluated, changed or even discarded over time.
Put differently, originalism has always proffered a false alternative: either the judge sticks closely to historical data points, or else the judge is utterly untethered, free to apply the judge’s own “preferences” or “policy views” or “values.” This false alternative (unfortunately much on display in the originalist mini-essays, labeled as concurrences, by Justices Gorsuch and Kavanaugh) overlooks that there is a third path: the elaboration and development of rational principles underlying the constitutional tradition, principles that are external to the judge because they are immanent in the tradition itself, and are thus not reducible to the judge’s own “preferences,” but that are also intelligible to legal reason and identified by irreducible legal judgment. It is heartening, if surprising, to see this distinctly classical approach reappear at the Supreme Court.
I don't think Justice Thomas's approach is even good originalism. Originalism is supposed to decide cases on the public meaning of the text. But a constitutional text may have a broader or narrower scope than the regulatory framework existing when the text was adopted. There's no inherent reason to believe that when the Second Amendment was adopted, the meaning of that text was to preserve exactly the regulatory environment that then existed and to allow, in perpetuity, only analogous regulations.
There are any number of reasons--having nothing to do with the constitutional right to bear arms--why legislatures at the time may have not enacted certain gun regulations. Maybe guns weren't widely used in domestic violence crimes back then so there was no need to ban guns from domestic abusers. Maybe certain regulations would have been procedurally impractical at the time (e.g., gun registration). None of that means that such regulations would have been understood then (or should be understood now) as inconsistent with the constitutional right to bear arms. By insisting that every gun regulation must have a historical analog to a regulation existing at the time of the Founding, Justice Thomas is interpreting the 2A text as constitutionally codifying the existing regulatory framework in 1789. That's not originalism. That's creating a law trapped in amber.
Justice Thomas's approach isn't even consistent with Justice Scalia's originalism, which required "not just history but judgment" and the application of underlying constitutional principles:
"What we have, then, is the most difficult case for determining the meaning of the Constitution. No accepted existence of governmental restrictions of the sort at issue here demonstrates their constitutionality, but neither can their nonexistence clearly be attributed to constitutional objections.
In such a case, constitutional adjudication necessarily involves not just history but judgment: judgment as to whether the government action under challenge is consonant with the concept of the protected freedom (in this case, the freedom of speech and of the press) that existed when the constitutional protection was accorded." McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 514 U. S. 334, 375 (1995) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
What a magnificent essay to elucidate the fundamental difference between deploying data points in applying Constitutional Principles as “trapped amber” [John Roberts] - a translucent fossilized resin produced by extinct coniferous trees in Neolithic times - in circumstances and conditions that have vastly changed.
Apart from the physical FACT that 2024 is not 1791 when 2nd was ratified, a domestic violence perpetrator is the precise opposite of “well regulated” by the least stringent of psychological testing; as well, a domestic violence victim is not a Red Coat by the most feral imagination even if he or she were to don a fire-engine red jacket.
Let alone for “data points” in his legal methodology, Thomas selected irrelevant points to rationalize his dissent opinion. In 1791, domestic violence did not come under the penumbra of 2rd Amendment protection.
I mark these words by the Prof: "The classical approach holds that principles are enduring, but that as circumstances change, doctrine must itself “change in order to remain the same”
I reiterate the central point of the essay: “The elaboration and development of rational principles underlying the constitutional tradition, principles that are external to the judge because they are immanent in the tradition itself, and are thus not reducible to the judge’s own ‘preferences’, but that are also intelligible to legal reason and identified by irreducible legal judgment.”
Yes, heartening indeed to see not only a classical approach reappear at the Supreme Court, but finally to see that the FACTS surrounding the enactment of the 2nd are visible to the men and women in the Highest Court are within normal limits of what I personally regard as common sense and sensibilities.